Monday, September 1, 2025

Thinking Beyond: Jaspers on The Encompassing, Transcendence, and Philosophical Faith

After boundary situations and the “loving struggle” of communication, Jaspers leads us toward the most difficult, yet perhaps the most necessary, part of his thought: how to speak about what lies beyond us. He calls this dimension Transcendence. It is not an object of knowledge, nor a set of doctrines. Rather, it is what we encounter whenever explanation reaches its limit, whenever freedom and responsibility press upon us in ways that no scientific or rational system can capture. To philosophize, for Jaspers, is always to circle around this beyond, without ever capturing it fully.


The Encompassing

One of Jaspers’ most ambitious concepts is the Encompassing (das Umgreifende). He proposes that reality appears to us in several “modes”—for example, as empirical objects, as consciousness, as spirit, and as Existenz. Each of these modes is real and important, but none is ultimate. Each leads us, if we reflect deeply, to something beyond itself. The Encompassing is his way of naming the horizon within which all these modes appear and which itself cannot be turned into an object.

Think of it this way: I can describe the world of objects with science, I can reflect on my own consciousness with psychology, I can cultivate culture and values as spirit, and I can confront myself as Existenz in freedom. But in each case, there remains something more, something I cannot pin down but which “encompasses” my attempts. Jaspers’ philosophy is a constant reminder that every stance is partial, that the whole can never be possessed.


Transcendence and the Ciphers

Here enters the idea of Transcendence. At the boundaries of every mode of the Encompassing, we meet a beyond that cannot be contained in concepts. We cannot prove it; we can only point to it. Jaspers insists that philosophy should neither collapse into dogmatic theology nor retreat into silence. Instead, we can approach transcendence through what he calls ciphers (Chiffren).

Ciphers are symbols, images, works of art, religious myths, or even personal experiences that hint at transcendence without exhausting it. A painting may become a cipher when it awakens in us a sense of the infinite. A line of poetry may suddenly disclose depth that no paraphrase can capture. A religious ritual may work as a cipher, even for someone who does not accept its dogmatic claims. The power of ciphers lies in their openness: they point, but never dictate.


Philosophical Faith and The Cipher

All this culminates in Jaspers’ notion of philosophical faith. Faith, for him, is not assent to dogma or revealed truths. It is an attitude of trust in transcendence, a willingness to live oriented toward what exceeds us. Philosophical faith means saying “yes” to the mystery without pretending to possess it. It is faith purified of authoritarian claims, yet still engaged, hopeful, and responsive.

This is what makes Jaspers’ project so distinct. He refuses the arrogance of absolute knowledge but also resists the despair of nihilism. He proposes a middle path: reason that is aware of its limits, and faith that is free of coercion. In this balance, he sees the possibility of a truly human existence—open to transcendence, yet humble about what can be said.

Consider how Jaspers might read a painting by Van Gogh. Objectively, it is canvas and paint. Art history can analyze its style, psychology can speculate about the artist’s mind. But when I stand before it and feel it disclosing a depth that cannot be reduced to technique or biography, it becomes a cipher of transcendence. I cannot claim to know “what it means” once and for all; I can only stand within the openness it creates. That is philosophical faith in action.


Beyond the Dogmatic Divide

Jaspers’ approach here is deeply relevant in a plural world. On the one hand, many people crave certainty—religious or secular systems that promise the final truth. On the other hand, many give up on transcendence altogether, reducing reality to what can be measured. Jaspers offers a third path: to live faithfully toward the beyond, to embrace ciphers as invitations, and to remain in dialogue without closure.

In this sense, his philosophy is not only existential but also spiritual, though without belonging to a particular religion. It asks us to think beyond what we can prove, not to escape the world but to live in it more fully, with humility, wonder, and courage.

Argue Like You Love Me: Jaspers on Communication, The Loving Struggle and Existential Truth

If boundary situations awaken us to our finite freedom, Karl Jaspers insists that this awakening cannot remain a solitary affair. Unlike Kierkegaard, who often portrays the individual before God in radical solitude, Jaspers claims that Existenz only comes to light in communication with others. The human being is not merely a self-contained subject who occasionally interacts with others; rather, communication is the very medium in which truth emerges. To seek truth is to enter what Jaspers calls the “loving struggle” (liebender Kampf)—a dialogue in which both partners risk themselves in openness, without coercion, and in mutual respect.


Object-Truth and Existential Truth

To see why Jaspers makes so much of communication, we need to distinguish between two kinds of truth. First, there is objective truth: the kind delivered by science, history, or logic. Objective truth concerns facts about the world that can be checked, tested, and agreed upon regardless of personal perspective.

But Jaspers argues that another dimension of truth exists, which he calls existential truth. This is not about neutral facts but about the truth of one’s being: how I live, how I respond to boundary situations, how I orient myself toward freedom and transcendence. Such truth cannot be isolated in formulas or data points; it must be lived and tested in encounter.

And here communication is essential. Objective truths can be written in textbooks, but existential truth requires dialogue, because it concerns freedom and selfhood—realities that only come alive when shared and confronted by another person.


The Loving Struggle

Jaspers’ most original image for genuine communication is the “loving struggle.” At first glance, the phrase seems contradictory: how can struggle and love coexist? For him, love without struggle would collapse into sentimentality or conformity; struggle without love would turn into hostility or domination. True communication, however, is both: it is the clash of convictions held with passion, combined with a mutual commitment to respect the other’s freedom.

This means that genuine dialogue is not about persuasion or victory. It is about risking oneself—laying bare one’s deepest commitments—while at the same time listening so openly that one could be changed. The goal is not agreement but illumination. In the friction of dialogue, the partners discover limits, test freedoms, and sometimes glimpse transcendence.


Humility Against Dogmatism and Relativism

The “loving struggle” is Jaspers’ antidote to two familiar temptations: dogmatism and relativism. Dogmatism insists that one side already possesses the whole truth, rendering dialogue unnecessary. Relativism, in contrast, claims that all views are equally valid, making dialogue pointless. Jaspers steers between them. For him, communication is necessary precisely because we cannot claim final truth; yet it matters because some ways of living and thinking open us more fully to freedom and transcendence than others. The result is a kind of epistemic humility: I do not own the truth, but through our struggle I may participate in it more deeply.


A Culture of Communication

Jaspers was writing in a Europe torn by ideological fanaticism and the ruins of war. His insistence on communication was not merely philosophical but political. He saw in genuine dialogue a model for democratic culture: citizens treating one another as free beings, refusing to reduce each other to categories, and resisting the temptation to impose truth by force. In this sense, communication is both existential and civic: it forms the foundation of humane community.

Imagine a heated conversation about a moral or political issue—say, climate change, or justice in war. Each participant has strong convictions. In the usual mode of debate, the goal is to win. But in Jaspers’ sense, the goal is to risk oneself: to state one’s view clearly and firmly, yet remain open enough that the other’s words might reshape one’s horizon. This requires courage, humility, and respect. Even if agreement never comes, both participants may leave with a deeper sense of their own commitments and a sharper awareness of freedom. That is existential truth in action.


The Risk and the Gift

To communicate in Jaspers’ sense is to risk misunderstanding, rejection, even transformation. But it is also to receive the gift of being seen and addressed as a free being. Communication is not the background of philosophy; it is philosophy itself at work. Just as boundary situations expose the fragility of life, communication exposes the fragility of truth. It can never be possessed once and for all; it must always be enacted, here and now, between living persons.

For Jaspers, then, philosophy without communication is an illusion. Truth is not a treasure hidden in solitude but a fire kindled between us. To argue like you love me is not just a clever phrase—it is the essence of human freedom lived in dialogue.

Sunday, August 31, 2025

When Explanation Breaks: Jaspers on Boundary Situations (Grenzsituationen)

If philosophy for Jaspers begins as orientation, then it deepens at the point where orientation falters—where no map can guide us, and no scientific formula can save us. Jaspers names these moments Grenzsituationen, boundary situations. They are not exotic philosophical puzzles but ordinary, unavoidable features of human life: death, chance, guilt, struggle. Everyone meets them, and no amount of progress or cleverness can erase them. They are “boundaries” not because they block us entirely, but because they mark the edges of explanation. And it is precisely here, at the edges, that Jaspers believes human freedom and Existenz become visible.


The Four Boundary Situations

Jaspers identifies several paradigmatic boundaries. The first and most obvious is death. However much medicine extends life, we remain finite beings. Death is not only an event at the end of life but a presence shaping every decision. To live authentically means living under the horizon of finitude.

The second is struggle. Human life cannot be imagined without conflict—with others, with nature, with ourselves. Struggle is not simply a technical problem to be solved but a permanent feature of existence.

The third is guilt. However responsible or moral we try to be, we are bound to fall short. We fail others, we act from mixed motives, we are implicated in injustices larger than us. For Jaspers, this sense of guilt is not pathological but revealing: it shows us that we are never the masters of pure innocence.

Finally, there is chance. The accidents of birth, history, and circumstance condition everything about us—yet they remain beyond our control. To live is to accept contingency, to acknowledge that much of what shapes us is not chosen.


Why Limits Matter

At first glance, these boundary situations sound bleak, even paralyzing. But Jaspers turns the perspective upside down. What looks like failure is in fact the gateway to depth. When we try to explain death scientifically, or rationalize guilt away, or reduce chance to probability, we reach a dead end. The tools of knowledge run out. In that moment of breakdown, something new becomes possible: the illumination of Existenz.

For Jaspers, we do not discover who we truly are in our successes—those can always be explained by psychology, biology, sociology. We discover ourselves in moments of shipwreck, when the familiar coordinates collapse. It is then that we are called to freedom, to decision. Boundary situations strip away illusions of mastery and force us to face ourselves.


Not Irrational, but Trans-Rational

Critics sometimes suspect that Jaspers is smuggling irrationalism into philosophy: does he want us to abandon reason when we face death or guilt? His answer is subtle. He is not asking us to give up reason but to recognize its limits. Science can describe the biological processes of dying, but it cannot tell me how to die well. Psychology can analyze the roots of guilt, but it cannot resolve my responsibility. Philosophy, for Jaspers, is precisely this work of stepping beyond the objectifying stance of knowledge toward an existential awareness that is still rational—what he calls a “reason become aware of its boundary.”

Each limit situation issues an invitation. Death invites us to live each day as finite and precious. Struggle invites us to take responsibility and act, even when no outcome is guaranteed. Guilt invites us to humility and reconciliation. Chance invites us to gratitude, acceptance, and the courage to shape freedom from contingency. None of these invitations are forced; we can evade them by distraction or denial. But in doing so we lose the possibility of becoming authentic Existenz.


The Stage for Freedom

It may help to consider an example. Imagine someone facing a sudden illness. At first, the person turns to doctors, treatments, statistics. These are important, but soon the realization comes: no calculation can remove the fact of mortality. Here the boundary situation of death presses in. Jaspers would say that in this moment, the person is offered a choice: to sink into despair or to recognize finitude as the condition for a deeper freedom—to live fully now, in communication with others, under the shadow of death. The illness is no less tragic, but it becomes the site of existential awakening.

Jaspers’ message is paradoxical: our limits are the very ground of our freedom. Far from shrinking us, they disclose that existence cannot be exhausted by scientific explanation. In death, guilt, struggle, and chance, we encounter the space where freedom and responsibility appear. To ignore these limits is to live superficially; to face them is to begin the philosophical life.

This is why Jaspers insists that philosophy must always return to the edge, where explanation breaks. It is there that Existenz, fragile yet irreducible, shines most clearly.

Starting at the Edge: Karl Jaspers - Life, Method and Philosophy

Karl Jaspers is one of those philosophers who often gets mentioned in the same breath as Heidegger or Sartre, yet remains curiously under-read. Part of the reason is that his work resists easy classification. He was not a system-builder in the style of Hegel, nor did he write manifestos like Sartre. His voice is quieter, more probing, sometimes even hesitant. But it is precisely this tone that makes him such a valuable guide for our time. Jaspers’ philosophy does not claim to solve the mysteries of existence; it seeks instead to illuminate the conditions in which we face those mysteries honestly, without shortcuts or illusions.

To understand why Jaspers matters, it helps to begin with the arc of his life. Born in Oldenburg in 1883, he first trained as a physician and made his name in psychiatry. His early research on mental illness—later published as General Psychopathology—was revolutionary: he rejected the reduction of patients to mere biological dysfunction and insisted on understanding their inner world. This sensitivity to the lived experience of individuals would remain the hallmark of his philosophy. Yet Jaspers eventually grew dissatisfied with psychiatry, sensing that medicine, science, and even psychology had limits. They could explain the mechanisms of life, but they could not touch the core of human existence—freedom, guilt, mortality, the search for meaning. Out of this dissatisfaction grew his lifelong project: philosophy as orientation in the world and as illumination of what he called Existenz.


Philosophy as Orientation

For Jaspers, philosophy is not a luxury or an academic discipline in the narrow sense. It is an act of orientation: a way of finding our bearings in a reality that is often confusing, contingent, and overwhelming. Science offers maps of the world, but they are maps of objects—of things measurable, quantifiable, predictable. Philosophy, by contrast, orients us as subjects who must live and decide in that world. It is the practice of asking where we stand, how we should act, and what lies beyond what we can know. In this way Jaspers brings philosophy down to its ancient task: helping us live, not merely cataloging knowledge.

This orientation requires a special vocabulary. Central to it is the idea of Existenz—not existence in the everyday sense, but existence as the self who becomes itself in freedom and decision. One could say Existenz is the self at its most authentic, the dimension of the human that can never be fully captured by scientific description or social roles. Philosophy, then, is the attempt to “illuminate” this Existenz—not to define it once and for all, but to shed light on its possibilities.


Limits and the Encompassing

Jaspers also insisted that we constantly encounter limits. No matter how much knowledge we accumulate, there are boundary situations—death, guilt, suffering, chance—where explanation fails us. At these edges, the project of orientation takes a new shape: instead of mastering the world, we are confronted with the mystery of being itself. For Jaspers, this is not a failure but an opening. In the very moment when knowledge reaches its limit, philosophy can awaken us to freedom and to what he calls the Encompassing—the whole within which we live, think, and act, yet which always exceeds our grasp.

Already here we sense the unique timbre of Jaspers’ thought: he is neither dismissive of science nor content with it. He honors reason but insists on its humility. His philosophy is not an alternative to rational thought but a deepening of it, a way of recognizing where reason ends and freedom begins.


Jaspers's Invitation

It is tempting to place Jaspers neatly in the existentialist camp, but this obscures as much as it clarifies. Compared to Heidegger, Jaspers resists the temptation to make metaphysics out of existence; compared to Sartre, he avoids the polemical style and the reduction of freedom to mere choice. Jaspers stands apart in his insistence on communication, transcendence, and faith—not faith as dogma, but what he calls philosophical faith, a trust in transcendence without claims to final truth. In this way, he is both more modest and, perhaps, more radical than his better-known peers.

To begin reading Jaspers, then, is to accept an invitation. He does not offer a system to be memorized but a set of paths to walk. His writing asks us to look at our own lives, at the moments where science and common sense fail, and to consider how freedom, communication, and transcendence might appear there. He is a philosopher of beginnings—of standing at the edge where certainty falters, and asking what it means to live responsibly, truthfully, and in dialogue with others.

In this series, we will follow Jaspers step by step, beginning with the experience of limits and moving toward his vision of truth, transcendence, and responsibility. The hope is not only to understand him but to find in his thought a companion for our own questions. Because for Jaspers, philosophy is never about answers stored in books; it is about the way we orient ourselves in the fragile, unpredictable, yet deeply meaningful business of being human.


Understand More:





Saturday, August 30, 2025

From Symbolic Anthropology to Digital Rituals: ‘Body Ritual among the Nacirema’ Revisited

In 1956, Horace Miner published a short anthropological essay that continues to surface in classrooms, syllabi, and internet searches alike: "Body Ritual among the Nacirema". A satire masked as ethnography, the piece describes the bizarre, elaborate hygiene practices of a North American group—the Nacirema—who engage in daily rites involving "mouth-rites," ritual ablutions, and visits to the "holy-mouth-man."

The twist, of course, is that the Nacirema are simply Americans spelled backward. By adopting the detached tone of the cultural outsider, Miner exposed the implicit absurdities and unexamined rituals of mid-century American life. What appeared exotic was, in fact, ordinary. The essay became an instant classic of symbolic anthropology, a field that examines how rituals and symbols construct meaning within a culture.


Theory Snapshot: Symbolic Anthropology

Symbolic anthropology, particularly as shaped by figures like Clifford Geertz and Victor Turner, treats culture not as a fixed set of practices but as a constantly shifting system of signs, stories, and rituals. It asks us to decode gestures, ceremonies, and symbols the way one might read a novel or a sacred text. Culture, in this view, is semiotic: it speaks.

Geertz famously described culture as "webs of significance" spun by humans themselves. The role of the anthropologist, then, is to interpret those webs—to understand what a cockfight in Bali or a mouth-rite in North America means within its specific symbolic universe. Turner's contributions emphasized performance, liminality, and the transformative potential of ritual. Together, their work positions symbolic anthropology as a tool not just for studying the Other, but for holding a mirror to ourselves.


Case in Point: The Digital Rituals of Today

Fast forward to the present day—an age of TikTok challenges, curated Instagram stories, and hyper-personalized wellness routines. What would Miner make of us now, endlessly documenting ourselves, performing to the algorithm, and crafting online selves that are both public and private shrines?

Consider the selfie: a repeated, stylized act, often taken in similar poses or contexts, then offered to the digital collective for validation. It is both intimate and performative, sacred and mundane. Or think of the viral hashtag challenge, where participants replicate a behavior (a dance, a prank, a transformation) in highly structured ways, often with a prescribed soundtrack and aesthetic. These aren't just trends; they are rituals, complete with rules, symbolic objects (the ring light, the filter, the branded hashtag), and public performances that reinforce group identity and social norms.

Even the language we use—"going viral," "content creator," "followers"—carries the trace of the sacred and ceremonial. Like the Nacirema’s shrine-box filled with magical potions (a.k.a. the medicine cabinet), we curate altars of self-presentation: apps, gear, lighting, captions. We anoint ourselves with filters, seek blessings in the form of likes, and perform penance through digital detoxes.

The rituals are repetitive, emotionally charged, and often tied to invisible economies of reward: not just followers or influence, but social recognition, belonging, and existential reassurance. In a fragmented world, digital rituals anchor us in shared rhythms.


Us, The Contemporary Nacirema 

Symbolic anthropology urges us to read culture not at face value but as layered, coded, mythic. What Miner's essay made clear—and what digital rituals underscore today—is that modernity does not escape ritual; it reinvents it, often in faster, more dispersed forms.

In an era where online behavior is often dismissed as superficial or performative, symbolic anthropology invites a deeper interpretation. What do our digital rites say about our values, fears, and aspirations? How do they mediate the sacred and the profane in a supposedly secular world? Who gets to participate in these rituals, and who gets excluded?

Minimally, they offer continuity. Maximally, they construct meaning. Just as the Nacirema's obsessive mouth-care hinted at deeper anxieties about purity, status, and control, our digital performances reveal submerged narratives about identity, visibility, and self-worth.

To study the Nacirema now is to see ourselves more clearly—not just through satire, but through the enduring lens of ritual. It reminds us that culture, even our own, is always stranger than it seems.

The Flesh of the World: Merleau-Ponty’s Late Ontology

By the late 1950s, Merleau-Ponty felt that his Phenomenology of Perception had not gone far enough. Describing how the body structures perception still risked leaving intact the old oppositions between subject and object, inner and outer, self and world. What was needed was a deeper account of being itself—an ontology that could explain why these dualisms arise and how they might be overcome. His unfinished masterpiece, The Visible and the Invisible, takes up this task.


Reversibility and the Chiasm

A striking example guides his shift: the hand that touches another hand. When I place one hand upon the other, I am both the toucher and the touched. The roles can reverse in an instant, but they cannot be lived simultaneously. This reversible relation reveals a truth deeper than either subjective experience or objective description: the body is woven into a circuit of perception where the seer can be seen, the toucher can be touched.

Merleau-Ponty calls this structure the chiasm, borrowing the Greek word for a crossing or intertwining. Consciousness and world are not two separate orders that somehow connect—they are folded into one another.


The Flesh of the World

To name this deeper layer, he introduces the concept of flesh. Flesh is not matter, substance, or spirit. It is the elemental fabric of reality, the shared medium that makes perception and relation possible. My body is made of the same “stuff” as the world it perceives, and so there is no absolute gulf between subject and object. Instead, there is a continuous texture that allows for their reversible relation.

This ontology of flesh transforms phenomenology into a philosophy of being. The world is not an object before a subject; it is the very tissue in which subjects and objects co-emerge.

The idea of flesh dissolves the classical binaries that haunted Western thought. Mind and body, nature and culture, even self and other, are not radically opposed but variations within the same fabric. This does not erase difference but situates it within a field of intertwining.

The implications are wide-ranging. In ecology, it suggests a kinship between humans and the natural world: we belong to the same flesh, not as detached observers but as participants. In ethics, it grounds intersubjectivity in a shared being: the other is not radically alien but already inscribed in the fabric I inhabit. In art, it illuminates how painting, music, or poetry can disclose dimensions of reality inaccessible to science.


An Unfinished Vision

Merleau-Ponty died suddenly in 1961 at the age of 53, leaving The Visible and the Invisible in fragments. Yet even in its incomplete state, the work reveals the trajectory of his thought: from describing the lived body to articulating a new ontology where body and world, self and other, meet in the elemental flesh.


Merleau-Ponty and The Phenomenology of the World: Intersubjectivity, Language, and Expression

From the Individual to the World

After establishing the body as the ground of perception, Merleau-Ponty turns to the broader question: how does my embodied being connect me to others and to a shared world of meaning? If the body is my way of being in the world, then it must also be my way of being with others. Perception is never solitary. It is already oriented toward intersubjectivity—the mutual recognition of embodied beings inhabiting the same field of existence.

This is not a matter of inferring that others have minds, as Descartes once worried. I do not reason my way to the existence of the other. I encounter the other directly through their gestures, expressions, and presence. A smile, a raised eyebrow, the tilt of a head—these are not signs I must decode but forms of meaning that my body immediately understands.


The Silent Language of Gestures

Merleau-Ponty gives priority to this pre-verbal communication. Before language, there is the dialogue of bodies. A mother and infant exchange looks and touches that already establish a world of meaning. A dancer’s movement or an actor’s posture can express more than a paragraph of words.

This insight helps us understand intersubjectivity without reducing it either to biological reflexes or abstract reasoning. We are open to others because we inhabit the same “flesh of the world,” and our bodies are attuned to the gestures of others as meaningful.


Language as Embodied Expression

From this starting point, Merleau-Ponty develops his rich philosophy of language. He resists the temptation to treat language as a neutral code or a transparent tool for transmitting ideas. Words are not just labels attached to ready-made thoughts. Language is a form of expression that brings meaning into being.

When a poet finds the right word, it is not a simple act of attaching language to a pre-existing idea. The idea itself crystallizes through the word. Similarly, when we struggle to articulate a feeling, we do not merely translate from inner sensation to outer sound—we discover what the feeling is by giving it form in speech.

Merleau-Ponty describes this as the difference between spoken speech (language already sedimented into conventions) and speaking speech (the living act of expression). In speaking speech, language is not a vessel but a creative force.


Art as the Revelation of Perception

It is no surprise, then, that Merleau-Ponty was drawn to the arts, especially painting. He wrote extensively on Cézanne, whom he admired for showing the world not as a finished object but as it comes into being through vision. For Merleau-Ponty, a painting is not an imitation of reality but a revelation of perception’s structure. The brushstroke discloses the way the eye dwells in color and form.

Art exemplifies the intertwining of perception and expression. Just as language makes thought manifest, painting makes visible the invisible act of seeing. This explains why artworks can strike us as more “true” than a photograph: they express the very way the world is given to us, rather than a mere reproduction of surfaces.


The Social Body and Political Expression

Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy also extends into the political sphere. If our very capacity to share a world depends on embodied intersubjectivity, then social life is rooted in the body as well. Politics is not simply a matter of institutions and laws but of how bodies encounter one another in public space, how voices are heard or silenced, how gestures of solidarity or exclusion shape the fabric of community.

This explains why he was drawn to Marxism in his early years—not because he accepted determinist doctrine, but because he sought a philosophy that could honor the lived, bodily reality of oppression and struggle. Later, as he distanced himself from dogma, he still maintained that politics must be understood as a field of embodied meaning, not as a chessboard of abstract forces.


Expression as Ontology

At this stage of his thought, Merleau-Ponty sees expression not as a secondary activity layered onto a silent world but as the very way the world becomes meaningful. Gestures, words, paintings, and political acts are all forms of expression that disclose reality. The world is not a mute background but an inexhaustible field that calls for articulation.


Why This Matters

Merleau-Ponty’s account of intersubjectivity and expression offers a way to think about communication, art, and politics without falling into dualisms. It helps explain why miscommunication is so painful: it is not simply a failure of codes but a fracture in the shared world. It clarifies why art can transform perception itself, not just reflect it. And it grounds the idea that social justice is not only about resources or rules but about recognition—whether bodies are seen, heard, and allowed to express themselves.