· After a
scientific revolution, “scientists are responding to a different world.” (p.
111)
· “[T]hough
the world does not change with a change of paradigm, the scientist afterward
works in a different world.” (p. 121)
· What
scientists “see” during their research depends on the normal science tradition
in which they operate. Therefore, the world that scientists “see” after a
scientific revolution seems incommensurable with the world they “saw” before
the revolution. (p. 112)
· “[S]omething
like a paradigm is prerequisite to perception itself.” (p. 113)
· Paradigm
shifts are unlike gestalt switches in the following respect: For gestalt
switches there is an external standard with respect to which the switch can be
demonstrated. However, for paradigm shifts “[t]he scientist can have no
recourse above or beyond what he sees with his eyes and instruments.” (p. 114)
· Scientists
themselves do not report the changes that occur as a result of scientific
revolutions as changes of “scientific vision” or “mental transformation with
the same effect.” The “evidence that the scientist with a new paradigm sees
differently from the way he had seen before” is “indirect and behavioral.” (p.
115)
· The
history of astronomy provides some of this “indirect and behavioral evidence”
that scientists “see differently” after a paradigm shift from how they “saw”
before. (pp. 116-117)
· Other
examples of this “indirect and behavioral evidence” comes from the histories of
the discoveries of electrical repulsion (pp. 117-118), oxygen (p. 118), and the
pendulum (pp. 119-120).
· According
to an alternative view, scientists do not “see” the world differently as a
result of a scientific revolution but rather simply interpret their
observations differently. This view is part of a philosophical paradigm. (pp.
120-121)
· The
history of science is one of the things that suggests that the “interpretation
paradigm” is “askew.” (p. 121)
· Scientific
revolutions cannot be reduced to mere reinterpretations of “individual and
stable data” for the following reasons:
1. Scientific
data is not stable. (p. 121)
2. The
process of transition from data related to an old paradigm to data related to a
new paradigm does not resemble interpretation. (p. 122)
3. Interpretation
usually (always?) presupposes a paradigm.
4. Interpreting
data can articulate a paradigm but not “correct” it. (p. 122)
5. The
“flashes of intuition” that often lead to a new paradigm “are not logically or
piecemeal linked to particular items” of experience based on the old paradigm.
(pp. 122-123)
· Scientific
data is not stable insofar as sensory experience is not “fixed and neutral.”
(p. 126)
1. There
appears to be no way to construct a “neutral language of observation.” (pp.
126-129)
2. The
operations and measurements that scientists typically perform are
paradigm-determined. (p. 126)
· The
measurements and “manipulations” that survive scientific revolutions change
either (1) in relation to the paradigm or (2) in concrete results. (pp.
129-130)
· An
example of how the measurements and “manipulations” that survive scientific
revolutions change in relation to the paradigm is how the work that chemists
did in investigating the law of fixed proportions changed as a result of the
acceptance of Dalton’s chemical atomic theory. (pp. 130-134)
· An
example of how the measurements and “manipulations” that survive scientific
revolutions change with respect to concrete results is how the measured weight
ratios of certain chemical elements in compounds changed as a result of the
acceptance of Dalton’s chemical atomic theory. (pp. 134-135)
See also:
Summary: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions/ Kuhn - chapter 1
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions/ Kuhn - chapter 9
Philosophy of Science - Summaries
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions/ Kuhn - chapter 9
Philosophy of Science - Summaries